differential geometry


0.1 Classical differential geometry

Differential geometryMathworldPlanetmath studies geometrical objects using techniques of calculus. In fact, its early history is indistiguishable from that of calculus — it is a matter of personal taste whether one chooses to regard Fermat’s method of drawing tangentsPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmath and finding extrema as a contribution to calculus or differential geometry; the pioneering work of Barrow and Newton on calculus was presented in a geometrical languagePlanetmathPlanetmath; Halley’s 1696 paper in which he announces his discovery that dxx=logx+C is entitled quadratureMathworldPlanetmath of the hyperbolaMathworldPlanetmathPlanetmath.

It is only later on, when calculus became more algebraic in outlook that one can begin to make a meaningful separationMathworldPlanetmathPlanetmath between the subjects of calculus and differential geometry. Early differentialMathworldPlanetmath geometers studied such properties of curves and surfacesMathworldPlanetmath such as: computing their lengths and areas, finding tangents, constructing evoluteMathworldPlanetmath, involute, and pedal curves, studying curvatureMathworldPlanetmathPlanetmath and osculating circlesMathworldPlanetmath, and finding envelopesMathworldPlanetmath and orthogonal curvesMathworldPlanetmath to a given family of curves. Of the various objects they studied, the cycloidMathworldPlanetmath deserves special mention. Originally discovered by Galileo, it seems to have been studied by just about every seventeenth century mathematician, much more than any other curve. Also, it is worth mentioning that the deep connectionsMathworldPlanetmath between differential geometry and mechanics which play a prominent role in contemporary theoretical physics also have their origin at this time — for instance, the fact that the problem of geodesicsMathworldPlanetmath on surfaces is related to the acceleration of particles was already to known to the Bernoullis, even though the significance of this similarityMathworldPlanetmath was not fully appreciated until Einstein.

0.2 Intrinsic geometry

A major turning point in differential geometry is marked by the appearance of Gauss’ memoir “Disquisitiones generales circa superficies curvas”. In this memoir, Gauss first proposes the intrinsic point of view in geometryMathworldPlanetmath. Since his idea of has intrinsic geometry has completely changed the outlook of geometry, it might not be inappropriate to spend some time discussing it.

Ordinarily, when we think of a surface such as a cylinderMathworldPlanetmath or a sphere, we concieve of a locus in space (3). However, imagine that, like blind ants crawling on a sheet, we were confined to a surface and had no direct knowledge of the space in which the surface was situated. What could we conclude about the surface on which we live? Obviously, such constructions as normals to the surface or osculating spheres which are situated in the ambient space would be meaningless to us. However, we would be still able to speak of the lengths of curvesPlanetmathPlanetmath drawn on the surface, the angle between curves, and areas of portions of our surface since these can be defined in terms of measurements which are made on the surface without recourse to the ambient space.

Considering differential geometry from this point of view, one comes to several interesting conclusionsMathworldPlanetmath. One is that certain surfaces, such as a portion of a plane and a portion of a cylinder are indistinguishable from the intrinsic point of view. This result can be something of a surprise because one is usually accostomed to thinking of planes and cylinders as rather different sorts of objects — planes are flat while cylinders are curved.

By itself this discovery is interesting, but perhaps not enough to fire a revolution in geometry. Hearing of it, one might come to the conclusion that intrinsic measurements alone are not sufficient to describe the geometry of a surface and, hence, the subject of intrinsic geometry is uninteresting. Further study shows that this is not the case. While one may not be able to distinguish a plane from a cylinder on the basis of intrinsic measurements alone, it is possible to distinguish a portion of plane from a portion of sphere solely on the basis of intrinsic measurements. Even more, it is possible to distinguish portions of spheres of different radii intrinsically. This, of course, is of interest not only because it shows that the study of intrinsic geometry is non-trivial, but because a quantity such as the radius of a sphere which is defined as the distanceMathworldPlanetmath from a point on the sphere to a point not on the surface (namely, the centre of the sphere) can, in fact, be deduced solely from measurements on the surface of the sphere.

To prove such results, Gauss used the concept of curvature. Since the idea of curvature, in one from or another, plays an important role in differential geometry to this day, let us say a few words about this key concept. The concept of curvature was developed in the eighteenth century as a measure how much a given curve or a surface deviates from being a straight line or a plane. In the case of a curve, the curvature may be defined as the second derivative of the normal angle with respect to arclength. In the case of a surface, the situation is a little more complicated — to describe the direction of the normal vectorMathworldPlanetmath, one needs two angles instead of one and one can choose to compute their directional derivativesMathworldPlanetmathPlanetmath along any direction tangent to the surface. Because of this, one obtains a 2×2 matrix of partial derivativesMathworldPlanetmath instead of a single number. If one changes the coordinatesMathworldPlanetmathPlanetmath used to describe the ambient space, then the components of this matrix will undergo a linear transformation. To obtain a quantity which does not depend on an arbitrary choice of coordinates and hence can be seen as describing geometric properties of the surface, one should consider the eigenvaluesMathworldPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmath of this matrix. These eigenvalues are known as the principal curvaturesMathworldPlanetmathPlanetmath of the surface.

The remarkable theorem which Gauss proved was that, whilst the principal curvatures cannot be determined from intrinsic measurements alone, their productPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmath can. This result, for instance, can be used to explain the facts we mentioned about planes, cylinders, and spheres. For a plane, the two principal curvatures equal zero. For a cylinder, one principal curvature is zero and the other is positive. For a sphere, both principal curvatures are equal and positive. Since the product equals zero for both the plane and the cylinder it is plausible that they are indistinguishable intrinsically. Since it is not zero for the sphere, it follows from Gauss’ theorem that the intrinsic geometry of the sphere could not possibly be the same as that of the plane and cylinder.

0.3 The concept of a manifold

The discovery of intrinsic geometry led thoughtful geometers such as Riemann (who was a student of Gauss), Clifford, and Mach to the conclusion that a “right and natural” approach to geometry should regard surfaces as geometrical spaces in their own right on a par with EuclideanPlanetmathPlanetmath and projective spaceMathworldPlanetmath. In the terminology of the mediaeval scholastic philosophers, one may say that they regarded the intrinsic properties of surfaces as “essential” and extrinsic properties as “accidental”. To properly develop geometry from such a viewpoint, they needed to start with a definition of surface which made no reference to any sort of ambient space. Their quest for such a definition led to the concept of a manifoldMathworldPlanetmath.

The genesis of this concept can be seen as a diasappearing act akin to that of the Chesire cat — just as the grin is all that remains of the cat when the cat disappears, so too a manifold is what remains when one starts with a parameterized surface and the space in which the surface is situated disappears.

A parameterized surface may be decribed as a suitable subset S3 together with a smooth bijectiveMathworldPlanetmathPlanetmath map from an open subset of 2 to S (which is called a parameterization of the surface). Moreover, (pay careful attention because this will turn out to be the key fact that makes the concept of a manifold possible) one can describe the same surface using many different parameterizations. Given two parameterizations ϕ:D12S and ψ:D22S of the same portion of surface, the two will be related by reparametrization; that is to say there exists a smooth bijection gϕψ:D2D1 such that ψ=ϕgϕψ.

By contrast, a manifold may be understood as a “parameterized set”. That is to say, a n-dimensional manifold M is a set together with a set of bijective maps from open sets of n to M (which are called coordiante maps). As in the case of parameterized surfaces, a coordinate map need not have the whole of M as its range. Moreover, we require that if two coordinate maps ϕ:D12M and ψ:D22M describe the same subset of the manifold, then there exists a smooth bijective map gϕψ:D2D1 such that ψ=ϕgϕψ. (Such a map is known as a coordinate transformationMathworldPlanetmathPlanetmath map or a transition functionMathworldPlanetmath.) To make this definition completely correct, we require a few more technical assumptionsPlanetmathPlanetmath but, in keeping with the spirit of this expsition, we shall not discuss them here and instead refer the reader to the entry notes on the classical definition of a manifold for a careful definition which takes technicalities into account.

As is obvious from the definition, if we make the further assumption that the objects of our set be points of Euclidean spaceMathworldPlanetmath and that the correspondence between points and pairs of numbers be continuousMathworldPlanetmathPlanetmath, we recover the definition of parameterized surface. However, we choose to refrain from making any asumption about the nature of the elements of our set. This freedom is exactly what allows us to regard two surfaces with the same intrinsic geometry as the same manifold — to obtain one surface, we specify one mapping of our set into Euclidean space one way and to obtain the other surface we specify a different mapping.

Objects other than surfaces can be manifolds. Most obviously, the Euclidean plane itself is a manifold since its points can be described by pairs of real numbers according to various coordiante systems (Cartesian coordinatesMathworldPlanetmath, polar coordinatesMathworldPlanetmath, etc.) Thus, the concept of manifold fulfills the desire of its inventors that Euclidean space and surfaces be of the same ontological status.

Less obviously and more curiously, the set of functions which satisfy the differential equationMathworldPlanetmath

f′′(t)+2f(t)+3f(t)=0

is also a two-dimensional manifold! The reason is that we can specify a solution of this equation uniquely by giving the values of f and f at a particular value of t and, by the theorem on continuous dependence on initial conditionsMathworldPlanetmath, f(t1) and f(t1) can be expressed as a continuous functions of f(t2) and f(t2) for any two numbers t1,t2.

Another example of a manifold is the group of affine transforms of the line. Recall (or look back at the sectionMathworldPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmath on affine geometryMathworldPlanetmath above!) that an affine transformationMathworldPlanetmath is of the form xax+b. Hence, such a transform is specified by giving the two real numbers a and b. A group like this one which also happens to be a manifold is called a Lie group. The study of Lie groups forms an important branch of group theory and is of relevance to other branches of mathematics.

Because of examples like the two just exhibited, it has been possible to apply the techniques of differential geometry in some rather unlikely settings. Once geometric notions like tangent spacesMathworldPlanetmathPlanetmath and curvature have been defined for manifolds (we shall indicate how this is done in the next section) then one can speak of such things as the tangent space to the set of solutions of a differential equation or the curvature of a group. While this may sound like a parlor stunt to demonstrate the generality of our definitions, it is more than that. By applying the techniques of differential geometry in such unlikely settings, mathematicians have been able to win insights and prove results about differential equations, groups and other mathematical objects which otherwise seemed intractable.

Before moving on to the next section, it might be worth pointing out that, when speaking of manifolds, it is customary to refer to the elements of the set as points and the real numbers which label them as points. The reader should keep in mind that this is merely customary terminology which derives from thinking of manifolds as a generalizationPlanetmathPlanetmath of parameterized surfaces and should no way be understood as suggesting that the elements of the set which comprise our manifold resemble points of a surface. As the examples show, they may be functions, transformations, or other mathematical objects.

0.4 Structures on manifolds

In order to discuss such geometric notions as angles and lengths and perform interesting geometric constructionsMathworldPlanetmath, one needs to equip one’s manifold with suitable structuresMathworldPlanetmath. In classical differential geometry, these structures were provided by the ambient space, but now that the ambient space has disappeared, they must put in by hand.

In placing structures on a manifold, the notion of reparameterization or change of coordinates which was built into the definition of manifold plays a crucial role. To explain how the process of imposing structures proceeds, let us start with a simple example — tangent vectors on a manifold. In classical differential geometry, a tangent vector 𝐯 to a surface S at a point 𝐩S is simply a vector in Euclidean space whose direction happens to be tangent to the surface at the point 𝐩. We could represent it graphically an arrow with its tail at 𝐩 which points along a tangent to the surface.

Of course, this description won’t do if we don’t have an ambient space in which to draw our arrow. Therefore, we need to look for a different description of our tangent vector. One possibility is to consider a description of the vector in terms of its components. However, to define the components of a vector, one needs a basis. If our surface is specified parametrically, there is a natural choice of basis vectors, namely

(xsyszs)

and

(xtytzt).

Of course, if we choose a different parameterization, we obtain a different pair of basis vectors. However, we can express one pair in terms of the other pair using the chain ruleMathworldPlanetmath. Thus, if a tangent vector 𝐯 has components (v1v2) with respect to the basis corresponding to the parameterization in terms of parameters s and t, it will have components (v1v2) with respect to the basis corresponding to the parameterization in terms of parameters s and t, where

(v1v2)=(v1v2)(sssttstt).

These observations form the foundation of the definition of a tangent vector to a manifold. To define a tangent vector 𝐯 to a two-dimensional manifold M at a point 𝐩, we shall associate a pair of numbers (v1v2) to every coordinate systemMathworldPlanetmath which describes 𝐩. The only restrictionPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmath we impose is that, given two coordinate systems, the pairs of numbers to be associated to these systems be related by the transform

(v1v2)=(v1v2)(sssttstt).

To define other structures on the manifold, we can follow a similarMathworldPlanetmathPlanetmath recipe:

  1. 1.

    Identify what sort of mathematical object will represent the structure in a coordinate system. In the case of a tangent vector, this was an n-tuplet of real numbers.

  2. 2.

    Identify how the this object is to transform under changes of coordinate system.

  3. 3.

    Define the structure as an assignment of mathematical objects of the type identified in item (1) to coordinate systems in such a way that the objects assigned to two coordinate systems are related by the transform identified in item (2).

Using this procedure, one can define all sorts of structures on manifolds, of which we shall consider only two more examples here. One example is the vector field. A vector field may be defined as the assignment of a vector to every point in the manifold. Given a coordinate system, we may specify such an entity by assigning an n-tuple of numbers to every point. In other words, in a coordinate system our vector field is represented by an n-tuple of functions. Upon making a change of coordinates, these n-tuples change according to the law presented earlier.

The second example is the metric field. Recall that in our discussion of intrinsic geometry, we considered measuring lengths and angles along the surface. Now, in Euclidean geometry, we may define the notions of length and angle in terms of an inner product. A metric field may be described as the assignment of an inner product for tangent vectors to every point of the manifold. Given a basis, an inner product can be described by a symmetricMathworldPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmath, positive-definite matrix. Hence, to define the notion of metric field, we will consider the assignment of a symmetric, positive definite matrix of functions to every coordinate system in such a way that the matrices assigned to two coordinate systems are related according to the transformation law for inner products under a change of basis.

Once we choose a metric field on a two-dimensional manifold, it becomes possible to study its intrinsic geometry as defined in the last section.

0.5 Sheaves and bundles

In order to understand the toatality of all possible tangents vectors, metrics, etc. one typically collects them into larger structures called sheaves and bundles. To understand how such constructions proceed, we will start by examining the fundamental example of the tangent bundle.

Last section, we desribed how a tangent vector is described in an intrinsic manner. Suppose we now want to consider the totality of all tangent vectors to a manifold. We could start by picking a point of the manifold and considering all tangent vectors based at that point. Since it is meaningful to make linear combinationsMathworldPlanetmath of tangent vectors with the same basepoint, the set of all tangent vectors with a common basepoint forms a vector spaceMathworldPlanetmath called the tangent space to the manifold at that point. As we saw earlier, vector spaces are manifolds because one can impose coordinates on a vector space by choosing a basis.

So our problem of describing the toality of all tangent vectors reduces to the problem of describing the totality of all tangent spaces. We claim that they form a manifold. Basically, the reason for this is that, to specify a tangent vector, we could give the coordinates of its basepoint with respect to a coordinate system on the manifold and specify which vector by its coordnates with respect to a basis for the tangent space at that point. This manifold whose points are tangent vectors to a certain manifold is known as the tangent bundle of the orginal manifold.

0.6 Back to Erlangen

When written, this entry will show how differential geometry may be understood as the study of invariantsMathworldPlanetmath of structures on manifolds under the group of diffeomorphisms. In terms of this definition, we shall introduce such geometries as Riemannian geometry, conformal geometry, Kahler geometry, symplectic geoemtry, contact geometry, teleparallel geometry, gauge geometry, etc. much as Euclidean, affine, and projective geometryMathworldPlanetmath were introduced above.

0.7 Differential invariants and local differential geometry

When written, this section will give the reader the flavor of the nuts and bolts of constructing the invariants which are supposed to describe geometrical objects according to the Klein’s principles. We shall mention such topics as Christoffel’s theorem and the Bianchi identitites and give some idea of the sort of topics which one considers in local differential geometry.

0.8 Global differential geometry

When written, this section will describe the Gauss-Bonnet theorem and some of its modern descendantsPlanetmathPlanetmath such as characteristic classes and index theorems.

0.9 The algebraic viewpoint

When written, this entry outline how one may take the algebra of functions of a manifold as a starting point and see that differential geometric notions correspond to algebraic constructions. In fact, one may reformulate differential geometry as the study of invariants of an algebraPlanetmathPlanetmath under the action of a group of automorphismsMathworldPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmath. Using this even more general definition, one arrives at such novel topics as the differential geometry of finite-dimensional algebras and non-commutative geometryPlanetmathPlanetmathPlanetmath.

0.10 Infinite-Dimensional Differential Geometry

1 Differential geometry on PlanetMath

When written, this section will include links to entries on differential geometry on PlanetMath.

Title differential geometry
Canonical name DifferentialGeometry
Date of creation 2013-03-22 17:13:50
Last modified on 2013-03-22 17:13:50
Owner rspuzio (6075)
Last modified by rspuzio (6075)
Numerical id 4
Author rspuzio (6075)
Entry type Topic
Classification msc 51-00
Classification msc 51-01
Related topic ClassicalDifferentialGeometry
Related topic DifferentialPropositionalCalculus